“Okakura, with Fenollosa, uncovered the statue Kannon… as
art. Previously, it had been hidden in a section of Horyuji Temple called
Yumedono for centuries. The whole history of Asia is stylistically condensed in
this sculpture.”
--Kojin Karatani, “Uses
of Aesthetics: After Orientalism” (pg. 156)
This quote particularly struck me as an illustration of Karatani’s
point, in his article, “Uses of Aesthetics: After Orientalism.” He details the
danger of “bracketing”[1] (because
it then becomes very difficult to “un-bracket”). He criticizes that
aestheticism recognizes only the intriguing, exotic, ornate, and beautiful of
another culture—simply another form of orientalism, bracketed into a
disillusioned “respect.” In the quote above, Karatani reveals, in action, aestheticism’s
failure to “unbracket”: “The whole history of Asia stylistically condensed in
this sculpture”—really? The whole
history of Asia? And how do you know the idol
is art in the first place? According to
Okakura, the statue was art; according to those who originally made and kept
it, the statue was a holy figure of the temple, not a piece for museum
exhibition (“the statue had been the object of religious awe rather than
artistic worship” [pg. 157]). In coining
the statue as ‘art,’ although he praised it with the highest admiration, he
decontextualized its intended worth, and became a colonialist by assigning foreign
interpretation and significance. Though perhaps unaware, he still completely
missed a non-European-centered view of this culture; his conception of art was assigned to their world. Regardless of whether the makers had intended it to be art or not, it became art by
Okakura’s notion of what art entails. This seems a form of benign
imperialism—but imperialism all the same. Instead of approaching a culture with
the mentality to hear from its real
individuals, we approach with the mentality to assign to its whole what we’ve already heard. In a
selfish form of esteem, we pull evidence to fill our established bracket of the
“foreign,” and get from it an intensified interest and admiration—which, of
course, brings us personal enjoyment. Karatani here critiques the unbalanced non-recognition
of individuals. He states that no side—western or otherwise—should dominate;
rather, social awareness should guide when to “bracket” and when to not,
leading to a balanced appreciation of other cultures, and recognition of each individual’s
validity as a real, individual human
being.
[1]
Internalizing an object’s identity based upon what that object’s identity is
assigned to be, and therefore “bracketing” other feelings normally associated
with it (pg. 151). We find
pleasure—based on the Kantian idea of our interaction with objects—in “bracketing”
normally negative or uncomfortable connotations; the greater the “bracket,” the
greater the pleasure. (“The act of bracketing displeasure gives pleasure on
another level…For instance, an evil that calls for ethical opposition can offer
pleasure in the subjective project of bracketing the ethical concern. For this
reason, aestheticism rather needs evil or abjection…The aesthetic stance, or
aestheticism, gets pleasure not from its object, but by bracketing various
reasons to the object.”) (pg. 151)
No comments:
Post a Comment